Subject
Identitarianism and populism
Félix Duque

In this text, occasionally drawing on examples from the ‘Spanish political laboratory’, Félix Duque undertakes a critical analysis of ‘identitarianism’, a term the Spanish philosopher uses to refer to the mystical and essentialist belief in identity responsible for two current political phenomena: populism and national populism.

Richard prince

Richard Prince, Untitled (Cowboy), 1991

 

On the face of it, nothing could be simpler than identity. So, even before we begin, we could consider the subject closed because there is nothing to see here. In fact, we already know from antiquity that identity is veritas per se nota, meaning evident in itself; no need, then, to give an account of (or reason for) it; it may be formulated negatively, with an exaltation of the corresponding proposition from the first principle of all thinking and being: the principle of non-contradiction.

But if, despite that, we come down from such lofty speculations, we must admit that for most mortals identity is more of a sentiment, on the grounds of which we all believe we are identical to ourselves. That verb can but set off alarms because at heart identity is neither a concept nor a sentiment, but a belief. Now then, it is just as hard to destroy a belief rationally in and by itself as it is to eradicate it sentimentally, given that the junction between a sought-after rationality (but which is to come and is always pending) and a sentiment paradoxically presupposed as a point of departure, always bears a powerfully emotive charge. And thus, in a reactive fashion, a desperate search is undertaken for a strange saving domination, in order to safeguard an existence, slaving away between the unforeseen and the unusual, and in a continual state of radically and absolutely ceasing to exist. And it is precisely this mechanism of compensation that goes beyond the continuous base of an ever-repressed emotivity (that of being aware of one’s own pending death and one’s ever-presupposed birth) to acquire an even more powerful, and at heart more irrational, emotivity a sensu contrario. That is, as we will have the chance to examine, aggravated identity as identitarianism. In 1959, Max Horkheimer memorably said something about German patriotism (or better still patrioterism) that could well also apply to any identitarian belief: ‘If patriotism in Germany is to be so feared it is because it has no reason to be (literally: because it lacks foundation: grundlos)’. As such: ‘There is no love to be found there, […] nothing other than a yearning for power (Machtgier) and aggressiveness.’1

"In Russia, meanwhile, we are witness to the rise of the part-shadowy, part-grotesque figure of Aleksandr Dugin (Vladimir Putin’s former adviser, running in exact parallel to Steve Bannon), whose mission consists of: saving Europe from liberalism and the satanic gay lobby."

Miriam Cahn

Miriam Cahn könnteichsein [couldbeme], 2015 © Photo: Courtesy of the artist, Galerie Jocelyn Wolff, Romainville and Meyer Riegger Gallery, Berlin and Karlsruhe

 

Language, incidentally, reflects the polysemy of this belief, as intimate as it is dangerous, by using a single term to underline the modality in which said belief is presented, that is to say the necessity (in as far as needing something and the fact that this something cannot cease being what it is).

Hence something as apparently abstract as identity is revealed as the most ardent of motives; the desire or conatus to be and to carry on being, in the knowledge that one is at all times exposed to ceasing to be, radically. And this on the varying levels on which the belief in identity operates: as an individual or as a member of a family or bloodline, or a nation, a State or, taking it to the extreme, the whole of Humanity. Except that the level of emotivity (and anxiety) decreases as levels of belonging increase, and thus national identity has to be consciously and artificially fostered, with warnings of the ever-present danger of it being lost, while the belief in a State identity, wherever it is not linked to the national one, has barely the ability to elicit any feelings of belonging and identity beyond those generated by the possession of a passport or national identity document, however much the Germany political scientist Dolf Sternberger may, in 19792, have coined the term ‘constitutional patriotism’, something Jürgen Habermas has been defending with particular determination ever since.3

According to this, other than in the case of individual identity (and the ever- possible loss thereof), other feelings of identity have been artificially created to confer sense on an ever-possible handing over of that individuality (to the extent of being willing to sacrifice oneself or to kill patriotically those who want to annihilate the group to which I belong). This artificial belief, interestingly disseminated through family upbringing, education and indoctrination, has its origin in a mythically-reinforced belief (e.g. the Fatherland as an arche). And then, that belief is theoretically dressed up as a logical principle, while also being emotionally coloured due to the conviction (however latent and repressed this may be) of the fragile and precarious character of this communitarian construct. All of the above may be summed up in one single motto, as pithy as it is peremptory: ‘Everything for the Fatherland’. This would be the essence of patriotism, just one step away from patrioterism.4

Faced with such dangerous extremism, it might be worth positing a definition of identity in a logical respect which, however, could also have an impact on the sentimental belief in that intimate identity. In other words: a subject is only identical to itself if its essential and universal aspect (that which it is), on affirming itself as such, recognises the specific and particular difference that makes it exist. That is to say, one cannot just be ‘Spanish’, but rather Spanish in the positive respect of being Castilian, or in the negative one of not-being Catalan or from Navarre, etc.

The crucial step from the belief in identity to the defence of identitarianism depends on this precise nuance. In fact, the identitarian does not accept that comparison, arguing that one is either Spanish in general and nothing else, or one is Spanish in truth by being Castilian or from Madrid, with the obvious danger that, faced with that dilemma, ones reaches a conditional clause of exclusion; if being Spanish is (solely) identified with being Castilian or from Madrid, then being Catalan or from Navarre is not to be truly Spanish, or it is to be so in a reduced and provincial manner.

In reality, it is quite clear what identitarianism conceals: it attempts to impose a mythical and essentialist belief (by which the ‘People’ continues to be the same throughout its history, thereby taking the form of Nation) over the factual reality of an ever-varying, ever-fortuitous existence, due to the contingencies of history. Contingencies which, today, particularly in the Western bloc, represent the transfer of power from the bourgeoisie, founded in mechanised industry, to a new emerging and disruptive financial and technocratic class, based on the absolutisation of information and communication technology. This means the progressive impoverishment of the so-called ‘middle classes’ and the replacement, at lower levels, of the proletariat by ‘zero contract workers’. This transformation from liberalism into global neo-liberalism, speculatively financial and digitally technocratic, further exacerbates the sentiment of a damaged identity, thereby giving rise, by reaction, to the blossoming of populism in its extreme manifestation: national populism.

Populism arises out of the confirmation of a certain heterogony of ends in post-industrial and neo-liberal societies which, always on the verge of collapse, do however paradoxically generate a gap of ever-increasing dimensions between the base and the power. Now then, taking account of the fact that, in democratic regimes, it is the base that chooses the power through elections, what populism advocates most of all is to win (or regain) the hegemony of the ‘people’ beyond the particracy which (according to the normal accusation) distributes that power, in a more or less surreptitious manner, it must be said, using certain core elements of what one might call ‘philosophical populism’.

"This transformation from liberalism into global neo-liberalism, speculatively financial and digitally technocratic, further exacerbates the sentiment of a damaged identity, thereby giving rise, by reaction, to the blossoming of populism in its extreme manifestation: national populism."

Most of all, with regard to the question of hegemony, and the creation of empty signifiers through a process of abstraction, by virtue of which the varying contents of ideals or symbols in which the differing strata of middle classes were recognised, and which are now the subject of disruptions that generate resentment, these come to be equal through a logic of equivalence of social conflicts. In the same way, the affected strata are globally identified as ‘people’, as opposed, with equal (but effective) simplicity, to the ‘caste’, in which the multiplicity of society’s actual, and the State’s ideological, apparatuses are included.

Furthermore, populist ‘logic’ tends towards the supposition that the relationship between, say, caste and people is, in Hegelian terms, the essential relationship between the whole and its parts, specifically characterised by the fact of the indifference which, from the outset, each side of the reflection has with regard to the other, in general. This is due to a leader being necessary to add something to the part; that is to say a relationship of equivalence serving as a general support for demands, by virtue of a particular faction that singles itself out, thereby bringing together the parts into a single whole.

1. The context against which this splendid aphorism is framed is that of post-National-Socialist Germany, when Horkheimer returned to the country from exile in the US. But it could also be applied to post-Fascist Italy or post-Franco Spain, without the latter, incidentally, having taken such decisive steps as Germany. In any case, the same thing may be said (and even more) for both of these nations as Horkheimer says about his homeland: ‘in no civilised country is there less reason (Grund) for patriotism than in Germany, nor is there any place where the citizens have criticised patriotism less, despite the fact that it was here that the most terrible acts were carried out.’ In: Hinter der Fassade, Gesammelte Schriften, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1991, vol. 6, p. 303.).
2. To mark the 30th anniversary of the Federal Republic of Germany.
3. See J. Habermas, ‘Ciudadania e identidad nacional. Reflexiones sobre el futuro europeo.’ In: Facticidad y validez. Trotta Madrid 1998, pp. 619-643.
4. We have two antithetical definitions of that sentiment. One, attributed to Dr Samuel Johnson who, according to his biographer James Boswell (The Life of Samuel Johnson, 1791), once said (in a phrase that became famous, even featuring in the Stanley Kubrick film Paths of Glory): ‘Patriotism is the last refuge of a scoundrel’. The other, much more prudent and ‘bourgeois’, comes from Hegel, who considered that patriotism: ‘is essentially the conviction that, in the everyday conditions and circumstances of life, one has got used to seeing the public good as the basis and end [of oneself].’ (Rechtsphil. § 268, Anm.; Werke. Suhrkamp. Frankfurt/M. 1970; 7, 413).

[...]